Blog

Between 2009 and 2020, Josh published more than 10,000 blog posts. Here, you can access his blog archives.

2020
2019
2018
2017
2016
2015
2014
2013
2012
2011
2010
2009

Schuette Plurality Cites Same Breyer’s Parents Involved Dissent That It Previously Criticized

April 22nd, 2014

Justices Roberts and Alito got some explaining to do. This is a bit confusing, so follow along.

In Parents Involved, Justice Breyer dissented. He claimed that in Seattle, there was a history of de jure segregation:

   1. Segregation, 1945 to 1956. During and just after World War II, significant numbers of black Americans began to make Seattle their home. Few black residents lived outside the central section of the city. Most worked at unskilled jobs. Although black students made up about 3% of the total Seattle population in the mid-1950’s, nearly all black children attended schools where a majority of the population was minority. Elementary schools in central Seattle were between 60% and 80% black; Garfield, the central district high school, was more than 50% minority; schools outside the central and southeastern sections of Seattle were virtually all white.

The plurality by Chief Justice Roberts (joined by Justice Alito), criticized this assertion of facts:

The dissent elides this distinction between de jure and de facto segregation, casually intimates that Seattle’s school attendance patterns reflect illegal segregation, post, at 5, 18, 23,15 and fails to credit the judicial determination—under the most rigorous standard—that Jefferson County had eliminated the vestiges of prior segregation. The dissent thus alters in fundamental ways not only the facts presented here but the established law.

15 Justice Breyer makes much of the fact that in 1978 Seattle “settled” an NAACP complaint alleging illegal segregation with the federal Office for Civil Rights (OCR). See post, at 5, 8–9, 18, 23. The memorandum of agreement between Seattle and OCR, of course, contains no admission by Seattle that such segregation ever existed or was ongoing at the time of the agreement, and simply reflects a “desire to avoid the incovenience [sic] and expense of a formal OCR investigation,” which OCR was obligated under law to initiate upon the filing of such a complaint. 

So, one would think that the Chief and Justice Alito do not find this part of the dissent accurate.

Then, we come to Schuette. The plurality, joined by the Chief and Alito, favorably cites the very portion of the Breyer dissent they criticized 7 years earlier!

Although there had been no judicial finding of de jure segregation with respect to Seattle’s school district, it appears as though school segregation in the district in the 1940’s and 1950’s may have been the partial result of school board policies that “permitted white students to transfer out of black schools while restricting the transfer of black students into white schools.” Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seat- tle School Dist. No. 1, 551 U. S. 701, 807–808 (2007) (BREYER, J., dissenting).

Scalia calls bullshit.

That conclusion is derived not from the opinion but from recently discovered evidence that the city of Seattle had been a cause of its schools’ racial imbalance all along: “Although there had been no judicial finding of de jure segregation with respect to Seattle’s school district, it appears as though school segregation in the district in the 1940’s and 1950’s may have been the partial result of school board policies.” Ante, at 9.2

2 The plurality cites evidence from JUSTICE BREYER’s dissent in Par­ ents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 551 U. S. 701 (2007), to suggest that the city had been a “partial” cause of its segregation problem. Ante, at 9. The plurality in Parents Involved criticized that dissent for relying on irrelevant evidence, for “elid[ing the] distinction between de jure and de facto segregation,” and for “casually intimat[ing] that Seattle’s school attendance patterns re- flect[ed] illegal segregation.” 551 U. S., at 736–737, and n. 15. Today’s plurality sides with the dissent and repeats its errors.

As does Sotomayor:

9 The plurality relies on JUSTICE BREYER’s dissent in Parents Involved to conclude that “one permissible reading of the record was that the school board had maintained policies to perpetuate racial segregation in the schools.” Ante, at 9–10. Remarkably, some Members of today’s plurality criticized JUSTICE BREYER’s reading of the record in Parents Involved itself. See 551 U. S., at 736.

The entire premise on which the Court managed to distinguish the political process cases was based on a reading of the Seattle case they disagreed with 7 years ago. This is wrong. The cases should have just been overruled. Not redefined in this surreal way.

Sunstein on the “Breyer Appendix”

April 3rd, 2014

In the Harvard Law Review, Cass Sunstein comments on Justice Breyer’s propensity add appendices to his opinions. He dubs it, the “Breyer Appendix.”

We might speak here of “the Breyer Appendix,” a worthy successor to the Brandeis Brief, in which Justice Breyer accompanies his opinions with an appendix citing a range of technical materials.6

6 See, e.g., Brown v. Entertainment Merchants Assn., 131 S.Ct. 2729, 2771–79 (2011) (Breyer, J., dissenting); Eldred v. Ashcroft , 537 U.S. 186, 267–69 (2003) (Breyer, J., dissenting); United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549, 631–44 (1995) (Breyer, J., dissenting); Rubin v. United States, 525 U.S. 990, 996 (1998) (Breyer, J. dissenting from denial of certiorari).

Add to that list a 15 page appendix in McCutcheon. Note how these are all dissents.

Of course, while referring to technical documents to defer to the government may make sense in the administrative context, this evidence is much less credible when balancing constitutional rights.

The “Breyer Appendix” is a cousin of the “Breyer Page,” where SGB monopolizes an entire page in the oral argument transcript.

Breyer’s First Amendment Right to “Collective Speech” in McCutcheon

April 3rd, 2014

Justice Breyer’s conception of liberty harkens back to the progressive era. Rather than viewing individual liberty, and rights, as ends onto themselves that should exist free from government interference, he sees liberty as important only so long as it serves some sort of governmental interest. Not that the government can limit speech when it has a compelling interest to do so, but speech is bestowed on people to serve that interest. Devoid of that utilitarian purpose, speech is no longer protected.

This utilitarian conception of freedom departs from the tradition of many prominent liberals, like Warren or Brennan, who sought to provide constitutional protections, even for non-democratic rights. In an Op-Ed I co-authored with David Bernstein in 2011 (feels like forever ago!), we argued that Breyer, on this front, most closely resembles Oliver Wendell Holmes. His views are most pronounced in free speech cases, as evidenced in his dissents in Brown v. EMA (herehere, and here), Sorrell v. IMS Health (here), and now McCutcheon v. FEC.

His discussion of precedent is grounded in Holmes’s vision of the marketplace of ideas:

 Speech does not exist in a vac- uum. Rather, political communication seeks to secure government action. A politically oriented “marketplace of ideas” seeks to form a public opinion that can and will influence elected representatives.

Next Breyer turns to a fellow Progressive, Justice Brandeis, and his concurring opinion in Whitney v. California.

This is not a new idea. Eighty-seven years ago, Justice Brandeis wrote that the First Amendment’s protection of speech was “essential to effective democracy.” Whitney v. California, 274 U. S. 357, 377 (1927) (concurring opinion).

To Breyer, we protect speech that is “essential to effective democracy.” He also cites Chief Justice Hughes for this instrumental view of liberty, that views speech only as a “means” to an “end” (emphasis added by Breyer):

Chief Justice Hughes reiterated the same idea shortly thereafter: “A fundamental principle of our constitutional system” is the “maintenance of the opportunity for free political discussion to the end that government may be responsive to the will of the people.” Stromberg v. Cali- fornia, 283 U. S. 359, 369 (1931) (emphasis added). In Citizens United, the Court stated that “[s]peech is an essential mechanism of democracy, for it is the means to hold officials accountable to the people.” 558 U. S., at 339 (emphasis added).

These might seem like laudatory goals, but when speech no longer serves to “secure government action” (whatever that is, and whoever determines that), the speech loses protection. This take a very, very cramped view of freedom. To Breyer, much like the Second Amendment, the First Amendment is a collective right.

Accordingly, the First Amendment advances not only the individual’s right to engage in political speech, but also the public’s interest in preserving a democratic order in which collective speech matters.

Think about that for a moment. What determines if speech is protected is whether it “preserve[s] a democratic order” for the “collective” good.  That is a very troubling vision of free expression. There is a lot of speech that may serve individualistic ends, and under strict scrutiny, it is the government’s burden to show why a compelling interest exists to limit that speech. It is not the individual’s burden to show that his expression is made in pursuance of some nebulously defined common good. Whether or not you agree with the majority’s (narrow) definition of corruption, Breyer’s discussion of free speech on pages 5-6 is troubling. I did a search for the phrase “collective speech” in the U.S. Supreme Court database, and the only hit was McCutcheon.

Rather than protecting speech, Breyer’s “collective” First Amendment limits it to ensure that others can be heard. According to Breyer’s views, campaign finance laws “strengthen” the First Amendment, by “creat[ing] a democracy responsive to the people”:

Rather, they are interests rooted in the First Amendment it- self. They are rooted in the constitutional effort to create a democracy responsive to the people—a government where laws reflect the very thoughts, views, ideas, and sentiments, the expression of which the First Amendment protects. Given that end, we can and should understand campaign finance laws as resting upon a broader and more significant constitutional rationale than the plural- ity’s limited definition of “corruption” suggests. We should see these laws as seeking in significant part to strengthen, rather than weaken, the First Amendment.

Again this is a collective First Amendment Right, whereby speech can be limited in order to promote other types of democratic speech preferred by the collective.

Even Breyer’s efforts to limit his opinion, and say that paying for speech is important, is still premised on this collective First Amendment right. The speech must relate to the “diffusion of ideas” or “the integrity of the electoral process.”

To say this is not to deny the potential for conflict between (1) the need to permit contributions that pay for the diffusion of ideas, and (2) the need to limit payments in order to help main­tain the integrity of the electoral process. But that conflict takes place within, not outside, the First Amendment’s boundaries.

It is somewhat ironic that the most vigorous defenders of free speech now on the Court are the conservatives. The Chief Justice’s majority opinion responds at several points to this “collective” First Amendment right. While Breyer cites Brandeis and Holmes for his First Amendment support, Chief Justice Roberts cites the apogee of liberal protection of free speech on the Warren Court, Cohen v. California (the “Fuck the Draft” case).

The First Amendment “is designed and intended to remove governmental restraints from the arena of public discussion, putting the decision as to what views shall be voiced largely into the hands of each of us, . . . in the belief that no other approach would comport with the premise of individual dignity and choice upon which our political system rests.” Cohen v. California, 403 U. S. 15, 24 (1971). As relevant here, the First Amendment safe- guards an individual’s right to participate in the public debate through political expression and political associa- tion.

This is the classic, liberal (not to be confused with classically liberal) vision of free speech–it means the government keeps its hands off speech, unless it has a really good reason. Roberts  directly responds to Breyer’s juxtapoistion of the “individual” and “collective” right of free speech.

The dissent faults this focus on “the individual’s right to engage in political speech,” saying that it fails to take into account “the public’s interest” in “collective speech.” Post, at 6 (opinion of BREYER, J). This “collective” interest is said to promote “a government where laws reflect the very thoughts, views, ideas, and sentiments, the expression of which the First Amendment protects.” Post, at 7.

Roberts emphatically rejects this collective First Amendment right, citing Alvarez, Wooley, and WV Board of Education v. Barnette:

But there are compelling reasons not to define the boundaries of the First Amendment by reference to such a generalized conception of the public good. First, the dissent’s “collective speech” reflected in laws is of course the will of the majority, and plainly can include laws that restrict free speech. The whole point of the First Amendment is to afford individuals protection against such infringements. The First Amendment does not protect the government, even when the government purports to act through legislation reflecting “collective speech.” Cf. United States v. Alvarez, 567 U. S. ___ (2012); Wooley v. Maynard, 430 U. S. 705 (1977); West Virginia Bd. of Ed. v. Barnette, 319 U. S. 624 (1943).

That’s exactly right. The First Amendment is not some sort of instrumental tool to protect government process. It is meant to be a shackle on government itself.

Second, who is to determine what speech is conducive to the collective good. This is a decision for individuals, not the collective.

Second, the degree to which speech is protected cannot turn on a legislative or judicial determination that partic- ular speech is useful to the democratic process. The First Amendment does not contemplate such “ad hoc balancing of relative social costs and benefits.” United States v. Stevens, 559 U. S. 460, 470 (2010); see also United States v. Playboy Entertainment Group, Inc., 529 U. S. 803, 818 (2000) (“What the Constitution says is that” value judg- ments “are for the individual to make, not for the Gov- ernment to decree, even with the mandate or approval of a majority”).

Third, I think Roberts gets it right that strict scrutiny already considers the general welfare, and does not protect any speech that unduly harms others. But that is the exception to the rule, not the basis itself. Speech is presumed valid unless it has negative social costs to others. But Breyer would make the preservation of positive governance the core of the right (seeing other similarities to his Second Amendment jurisprudence), rather than placing individual right at the core.

Third, our established First Amendment analysis al- ready takes account of any “collective” interest that may justify restrictions on individual speech. Under that accepted analysis, such restrictions are measured against the asserted public interest (usually framed as an im- portant or compelling governmental interest). As ex- plained below, we do not doubt the compelling nature of the “collective” interest in preventing corruption in the electoral process. But we permit Congress to pursue that interest only so long as it does not unnecessarily infringe an individual’s right to freedom of speech; we do not truncate this tailoring test at the outset. 

Roberts makes this point explicitly–the Court (mostly him) has held that “leveling the playing field” and improving the democratic process is not a valid interest to limit free speech. To Breyer, this is the primary reason why we have free speech–to ensure a level playing field.

ith the significant First Amendment costs for individ- ual citizens in mind, we turn to the governmental inter- ests asserted in this case. This Court has identified only one legitimate governmental interest for restricting cam- paign finances: preventing corruption or the appearance of corruption. See Davis, supra, at 741; National Conserva- tive Political Action Comm., 470 U. S., at 496–497. We have consistently rejected attempts to suppress campaign speech based on other legislative objectives. No matter how desirable it may seem, it is not an acceptable govern- mental objective to “level the playing field,” or to “level electoral opportunities,” or to “equaliz[e] the financial resources of candidates.” Bennett, 564 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 22–23); Davis, supra, at 741–742; Buckley, supra, at 56. The First Amendment prohibits such legislative at- tempts to “fine-tun[e]” the electoral process, no matter how well intentioned. Bennett, supra, at ___ (slip op., at 21).

Herein lies a fundamental disagreement over the individual, and collective First Amendment.

As we framed the relevant principle in Buckley, “the concept that government may restrict the speech of some elements of our society in order to enhance the relative voice of others is wholly foreign to the First Amendment.” 424 U. S., at 48–49. The dissent’s suggestion that Buckley supports the opposite proposition, see post, at 6, simply ignores what Buckley actually said on the matter. See also Citizens Against Rent Control/Coalition for Fair Housing v. Berkeley, 454 U. S. 290, 295 (1981) (“Buckley . . . made clear that contributors cannot be protected from the possibility that others will make larger contributions”).

Consider this passage on free speech from Breyer’s book, Active Liberty:

One the one hand, if strong First Amendment standards were to apply across the board, they would prevent a democratically elected government from creating necessary regulation. The strong free speech guarantees needed to protect the structural democratic governing process, if applied without distinction to all governmental efforts to control speech, would unreasonably limit the public’s substantive economic (or social) regulatory choices. The limits on substantive choice would likely exceed what any liberty-protecting framework for democratic government could require, depriving the people of the democratically necessary room to make decisions, including the leeway to make regulatory mistakes. [And in a sentence that could come from his dissent in Sorrell v. IMS Health] That, along with a singular lack of modesty, was the failing of Lochner. No one wants to replay that discredited history in modern First Amendment guise.” (pp. 41-42)

Breyer quite clearly views robust protection for speech, as a liberty interest, as no different from the liberty of contract protected in Lochner. And, except where speech serves some broader interest of supporting democratic governance, the state’s interests should trump. Granted, to Breyer democratic governance is a much more compelling interest than freedom of contract. This approach is akin to Holmes’s progressive view of free speech as important, so that competing views in the arena of ideas can work themselves out. But, there is no implicit or inherent value in freedom of expression by itself.

I wonder, and fear, that Breyer’s opinion may signal a shifting trend in broader thought on free speech on the left. With respect to speech, modern-day liberalism seems to be drifting away from protecting free speech, and more towards  state-imposed equality.

Ron Collins explored this dynamic in the ACLU’s decision not to file a brief in McCutcheon. Because the state has an overriding interest in campaign finance laws, the individual right to expression gives way. Steven Shapiro, the legal director of the National ACLU, alludes to this “divide.”

Ron and David are incorrect to suggest that the ACLU’s absence in McCutcheon v. FEC reflects a new sensitivity to “divisions” within the ACLU over the campaign finance question. The ACLU’s policy on campaign finance is among the most debated policies in the organization’s history. But despite repeated reexaminations, the ACLU has never wavered from its position in favor of public financing and against restrictions on political expenditures. The ACLU did, however, change its policy on contribution limits in 2010, stating for the first time that it would “not oppose reasonable contribution limits to candidates that are set at levels that allow candidates to amass sufficient resources to run effective campaigns.”

I imagine many in the ACLU from the Floyd Abrams generation can’t stomach this position.

The fact that Justice Ginsburg gave this opinion to Breyer, and not Kagan is telling. Kagan, could have provided a much more liberal vision of opposing campaign finance laws, while preserving the value and importance of free speech. Consider Kagan’s remarks on her voting with the majority in the video game violence case:

Among one of her most difficult cases, she said, was the constitutionality of the California law that would have banned the sale of violent video games to minors. The court in June struck down the law 7-2 using the First Amendment as the reasoning. “It was the case where I struggled most and thought most often I’m on the wrong side of it,” she said. “You could see why the government would have wanted to do this and you can see the kind of danger it was worried about, the kind of effects these extremely violent video games have on young people.” She added it was easy to see what the state was doing and it seemed reasonable. “But I couldn’t figure out how to square that with our First Amendment precedents and precedent is very important to me,” she said about her vote to invalidate the California law. “I sweated over that mightily.” Kagan also discussed other cases in the past year that have highlighted the court’s position on the First Amendment. “I think what you have to say, and people have been saying this, is this is a court that is extremely protective of the First Amendment and extremely protective of speech,” she said. “There is no question the court has a very expansive view of the First Amendment.”

I have to imagine Kagan held her nose signing onto parts of McCutcheon that reduces the First Amendment to an instrumentality of the state. In future opinions, the Kagan-Breyer divide on speech may drift wider.

Justice Breyer and Scalia Talk About Learning Property At Harvard Law School

January 14th, 2014

Oral arguments in Marvin M. Brandt Revocable Trust v. United States were something only a property nerd could possibly enjoy. There were discussions of easements, fee simples, divestments, shifting executory interests, and a host of other topics you no doubt have erased from your memory. You and Justice Breyer both.

During arguments, Justice Breyer was quite candid how he did not remember stuff from his first year property class at HLS, which we waxed somewhat  nostalgically about.

If I try to remember my property class, it vaguely was — which was a great class, A. James Casner, real expert.

Here is Casner’s 1990 obituary in the New York Times. He was on the faculty from 1938 till 1976!

And later, Justice Scalia (in criticizing Mr. Lechner again) notes that James Casner never taught him about the “limited fee.”

JUSTICE KENNEDY: Is there any doctrine in property law that if a right of access is granted and its to the exclusion of all other uses, it’s — it looks for all purposes like absolute control, that it ceases to be an easement and becomes a limited fee? I mean is there some magic that takes place in property law so that if there’s a grant that conveys such total control, is it construed not to be an easement?

MR. LECHNER: I don’t know of any.

JUSTICE KENNEDY: I’ve never seen it.

MR. LECHNER: Roads, highways are conveyed -­

JUSTICE SCALIA: Have you even heard of the term “limited fee” until this case? I never heard it.

MR. LECHNER: Well, I read these -­

JUSTICE SCALIA: James Casner didn’t talk to me about limited fee.

Lechner, who went to the University of Colorado Law School, had heard of it.

MR. LECHNER: I read these cases in law school so I was aware of the term. Thank you.

Good thing the Justices didn’t go to Yale. They don’t even require property!

Here, Justice Breyer struggles with distinguishing between shifting interests, divestitures, and condition subsequents:

JUSTICE BREYER: What they are saying, I think the government’s point is — the other side is saying, and I don’t remember the term of my property law. What’s the right term? It’s — you grant to A, black acre to A and his heirs; it’s a fee simple. But it’s subject to a shifting; it’s subject to divestiture, subject to a condition subsequent. What’s the right term?

MR. LECHNER: Well -­

JUSTICE BREYER: It shifts the — it shifts it back.

MR. LECHNER: A defeasible fee? Or implied conditional -­

JUSTICE BREYER: It could be. There was a technical term they used to have. But anyway, that’s what they’re saying.

I swear I’ve had this same conversation with a student trying to identify the relevant present and future interests in a case.

And this (near) Breyer Page stream of consciousness with references to Bracton is priceless (season should be seizin):

breyer-page

Breyer Brotherly Love At One First Street

December 10th, 2013

Justice Stephen Breyer’s brother, Charles Breyer, is a district court judge in the Northern District of California. Today, both brothers got supreme shoutouts in Mayorkas v. Cuellar de Osorio in a sharp colloquy with Mark C. Fleming.

JUSTICE BREYER: All right. Imagine Steven is a citizen. His brother Charles is not. So under 4 — and Charles has a son Joseph who is not. That will help you think about it. All right. So we’re under F4. Steven files a petition, the beneficiary is Charles. Charles has a minor son Joseph. Visa is granted, et cetera, for -­ not visa, you know, he’s given — everything is in order and now Charles has to wait about ten years or so. By the time he gets — at the time his number becomes namely for Charles, at that moment, we calculate Joseph’s age and it’s 24. All right. So your idea is that Charles is current. Everything is fine. He goes to the port or the office, wherever he’s supposed to go, and he brings Joseph with him. At that point, Joseph, since he’s no longer a child, has to come in under another category, and that category is going to be, I guess, 2B because Charles will be now — and Joseph will be unmarried over , right? Am I right so far?

MR. MITCHELL: I’m NOT comfortable referring to Your Honor by your first name or your brother by his first name.

(Laughter.)

“NOT” was capitalized in the original. Is that the Court reporters way of adding accents. No exclamation marks though.

Breyer responded in good spirits.

JUSTICE BREYER: This is an imaginary — he spells it with a V.

That’s not Stephen. It’s Steven!

Update: And that would be Mark Fleming, not Jonathan Mitchell who argued in the EPA case, who made the quip about the Brothers Bryer. Typo.