Blog

Between 2009 and 2020, Josh published more than 10,000 blog posts. Here, you can access his blog archives.

2020
2019
2018
2017
2016
2015
2014
2013
2012
2011
2010
2009

New “Single Sheet Classic” from the Green Bag – The Evarts Act of 1891

December 27th, 2016

Ross Davies has designed a “Single Sheet Classic” poster for the Green Bag about The Evarts Act of 1891, which created the initial nine regional circuit courts of appeals. The FJC offers this description:

In 1890 the House of Representatives approved by a large majority a bill to abolish the circuit courts, establish courts of appeals, and free Supreme Court justices from any circuit duties. In the Senate, William Evarts of New York offered a substitute that achieved many of the same goals but preserved more of the existing structure of the judiciary. The enactment of Evarts’ proposal in 1891 established a court of appeals in each of the nine circuits, but maintained the circuit courts to operate as trial courts alongside the district courts. The Evarts Act established an additional judgeship for each circuit and authorized the circuit justice, the circuit judges, or district judges to preside over each three-person court of appeals. In diversity suits and in several categories of cases before the courts of appeals, there was no right of appeal to the Supreme Court, although those courts could certify cases for a decision from the high Court. The Supreme Court justices also could grant a writ of certiorari to hear individual appeals. The impact of the act was quickly apparent as the number of new cases before the Supreme Court fell from 623 in 1890 to 379 in 1891 and 275 in 1892.

The poster illustrates drawings of each of the nine circuit courts of appeals, with fascinating tidbits about each.

 

The First Circuit in Boston:

The Second Circuit in New York:

The Third Circuit in Philadelphia:

The Fourth Circuit in Richmond:

The Fifth Circuit in New Orleans:

The Sixth Circuit in Cincinnati:

The Seventh Circuit in Chicago:

The Eighth Circuit in St. Louis:

And the Ninth Circuit in San Francisco:

What a cool poster. I can’t wait to hang it up!

Interviewed on 55KRC AM, Cincinnati to Discuss Unraveled and Obamacare

December 27th, 2016

On December 21, I was interviewed on the Brian Thomas Morning Show on 55KRC AM in Cincinnati (no, not WKRP) about Unraveled and Obamacare.

Federalism, Then and Now

December 26th, 2016

In my forthcoming Foreword to the NYU Journal of Law & Liberty, titled SCOTUS After Scalia, I trace the shifts on the right and left with respect to a host of constitutional issues, such as Article III standing and deference to administrative laws. One of the more pronounced changes reflects federalism. For example, in the Washington Post, Erwin Chemerinsky, Annie Laie, and Seth Daivs write that the Rehnquist and Roberts Courts federalism cases limit the Trump Administration’s powers over “sanctuary cities.”

Trump insists that he can force states and cities to participate in his plan to deport undocumented immigrants. But this ignores the 10th Amendment, which the Supreme Court has repeatedly interpreted to prevent the federal government from “commandeering” state and local governments by requiring them to enforce federal mandates.

For example, in Printz v. United States, in 1997, the Supreme Court struck down a provision of the federal Brady Handgun Violence Prevention Act that sought to require local officers to help enforce federal gun-control laws, including by conducting background checks. In an opinion by Justice Antonin Scalia, the court held that the act violated principles of federalism and the 10th Amendment for Congress by compelling state and local governments to comply with a federal mandate. Under the anti-commandeering principle, the federal government can no more require state and local governments to help it carry out mass deportations than it can require local officers to investigate and enforce federal gun laws.

Some have suggested that there is an exception to the anti-commandeering principle that allows the federal government to demand that states and cities turn over confidential information about undocumented immigrants. But this assertion misreads Supreme Court precedents. The court has held that Congress can require states and cities to disclose information where a statute also requires private parties to turn over the same kind of information. The court has never held that Congress can single out states and cities to share information with the federal government. That is the type of commandeering that the court repeatedly has found violates the 10th Amendment.

Nor can the federal government do indirectly — by threatening to withdraw federal funding from states — what it cannot do directly. In National Federation of Independent Business v. Sebelius, in 2012, the Supreme Courtstruck down a provision of the Affordable Care Act that required states to expand their Medicaid programs or lose the state’s federal Medicaid money. The court found the condition that Congress placed on states’ Medicaid funding unduly coercive and thus a violation of the 10th Amendment.

I was struck by reading these, as I recalled Chemerinsky has called for all of these cases to be reversed. Five minutes of research revealed some of Erwin’s prior writings.

In 2000, he wrote that Printz, as well as New York v. United States, should be overruled.

I believe that the ideal result in Reno v. Condon would have been for the Court to overrule the anti-commandeering principle. It is a rule not justified by the text, the Framers’ intent, historical practice, or sound constitutional policy analysis. Indeed, it often is counter-productive to the *829 Court’s goal of advancing state autonomy and is inconsistent with Congress’s powers under the Constitution. There is nothing in the text of the Constitution that mentions or even hints at an anti-commandeering principle. The Tenth Amendment’s text, of course, says only that Congress cannot act unless authorized by the Constitution, while states can act unless prohibited by the Constitution.42 Nor was the issue discussed at the Constitutional Convention. Neither New York v. United States nor Printz v. United States attempts to justify the anti-commandeering principle based on the Constitution’s text or Framers’ intent. Erwin Chemerinsky, Right Result, Wrong Reasons: Reno v. Condon, 25 Okla. City U. L. Rev. 823 (2000):

Erwin also wrote that the 10th Amendment places no limits on the spending power.

This is especially important as courts and commentators consider applying federalism principles to the spending power. Concern for protecting the states should not obscure the need to vindicate the authority of Congress to choose whether and how to spend its money. In this paper, I make three arguments. First, Congress’s spending power should be broadly interpreted. Second, the Tenth Amendment should not be applied as a limit on the spending power or on Congress’s ability to place conditions on its spending. Third, Congress should have expansive authority to require *90 that states waive their sovereign immunity as a condition of receiving federal funds. . . . *104 Thus, the Tenth Amendment should not be construed as limiting the ability of Congress to place conditions on grants to the states. Dole should continue to be followed. . . .  In this article, I have argued that the Spending Clause is different and that it should be limited by neither the Tenth nor the Eleventh Amendments. Erwin Chemerinsky, Protecting the Spending Power, 4 Chap. L. Rev. 89 (2001)

As for NFIB v. Sebelius, he wrote the spending clause analysis was made

“without reference to or invocation of constitutional theory” Erwin Chemerinsky, The Inescapability of Constitutional Theory Cosmic Constitutional Theory: Why Americans Are Losing Their Inalienable Right to Self Governance J. Harvie Wilkinson III. Oxford, 2012. Pp 3, 161., 80 U. Chi. L. Rev. 935 (2013)

He added that the Chief’s decision in NFIB:

“gave little guidance as to how to decide when conditions are too coercive and that will lead to a great deal of litigation.” Erwin Chemerinsky, It’s Now the John Roberts Court, 15 Green Bag 2d 389 (2012)

More broadly, Erwin wrote that federalism is “rights regressive” and does not promote liberty.

First, overwhelmingly, the Supreme Court’s federalism decisions are “rights regressive”-that is, they limit rather than enhance individual liberties. Part II of the article discusses this. Second, as a more theoretical matter there is no reason to believe that federalism will increase freedom. The traditional explanations for why the vertical division of powers enhances liberty do not withstand scrutiny.
Erwin Chemerinsky, Does Federalism Advance Liberty?, 47 Wayne L. Rev. 911 (2001)

Now, Printz should be used to prohibit federal commandeering of state law enforcement officials, and the Tenth Amendment should put limits on the withdrawal of funds for non-compliant states, as a means to promote the individual liberty of aliens subject to removal.

I emailed Erwin and asked if he still favored the Court overturning Printz, and still maintained that the 10th Amendment places no limits on Congress’s spending power. He replied was not entirely responsive:

I continue to believe that the Supreme Court’s federalism decisions are misguided and undesirable. But they are the law. And our oped argued under this existing law. I do not see any inconsistency.

That’s a huge leap from saying the decisions are utterly inconsistent with the Constitution and ought to be overruled–“misguided and undesirable” is quite a tepid response. But there is a broader issue at play here.

Attorneys, as advocates, are fully entitled, and indeed expected, to use whatever precedents are available to advance their clients’ interests–whether they agree with the principle or not. Professors, as scholars, have a different purpose. Though they have their own opinions, they are seeking some higher truth through their writing, or even advocacy as amicus or direct representation or editorial writing. Though admittedly the line is blurry, there is something disconcerting about an academic explicitly relying on a rules he deems absolutely wrong, and that he previously called on to be overruled. There should be an expectation that the case is consistent with the scholar’s understanding of the correct interpretation of the Constitution. In other words, they are not “hired guns” who will adopt whatever argument is available to serve their causes. (On a related note, Justices who do this–such as Justice Scalia’s sudden embrace of substantive due process in McDonald–are also subject to criticism).

I don’t mean to pick on Erwin here. He isn’t alone. There have been a rash of progressives who suddenly embraced federalism decisions that they previously argued were wrong. On the whole, I’m ecstatic that the Federalist camp is growing! But I don’t pretend for a second they really mean it. Had Hillary Clinton won the Presidency, they would have called on Justice Garland to cast a fifth vote to overturn Printz and a host of other decisions.

Stay tuned to my Foreword for a discussion of “constitutional consistency.”

My New Seven-Monitor Display and the Evolution of my Workstations

December 26th, 2016

Since December 2015, my workstation at home has had six monitors. That was not enough. So I recently upgraded to a seventh screen. In this video, I describe what function each screen serves.

Here as my workstation before the addition of the seventh monitor.

monitors

Here is my setup from April 2014. I had four 24″ HD LED flat-panels, mounted on two Dual-Monitor Desk Mounts. I rotated the one on the right, as it makes reading cases and document easier. And no, the palm trees are not native to Houston, but they make for a nice backdrop.

20140405_131751

From December 2012, during a brief period I kept two MacBook Pros rocking, and I added (yet another) monitor.

In case you are wondering, each screen has a dedicated function. My MacBook Pro screen is always trained on my gmail. The screen furthest to the left holds my Tweetdeck and Instant Messaging. The next screen to the right holds whatever document, or documents I am reading. The main screen in the middle contains whatever I am typing. The screen furthest to the right contains my Google Reader. My old Macbook Pro is used for ancillary stuff or testing things, and sometimes I will play a video or something on my Nexus 7 Tablet.

2012-12-27_12-20-52_202

From August 2012, when I moved to Houston, still with three monitors:

Here is my three-monitor display, which I had from June 2010, back in Johnstown, PA until 2012. Note that I still had paper. I’ve gone completely paperless, and it is amazing. Also, since then I’ve gotten rid of my Blackberry, and Google Reader is no longer with us.

On my laptop screen, I keep my e-mail window open. On the far left monitor, I have Pandora open (playing some catchy Lady GaGa song), Tweetdeck (featuring 2 twitter accounts and facebook), and Adium Chat. In the middle monitor I have Microsoft Word open (working on an Op-Ed for McDonald v. Chicago). On the monitor on the right, I have Google Chrome open (tuned to Google Reader). And, my blackberry keeps me posted with text messages and BBM (blackberry messenger for those uninitiated).

The University of Oregon Ducks the First Amendment

December 24th, 2016

On Thursday, I blogged about the dangerous precedents set by the University of Oregon’s decision that it could punish a professor for wearing black face at a Halloween party. In this post, I will discuss how the University’s report completely ignores precedents that are directly on point. This decision is not only dangerous, but is wrong.

Let’s start with Berger v. Battaglia, 779 F.2d 992 (4th Cir. 1985). In this case, an officer with the Baltimore Police Department performed musical routines in blackface while off duty.

In none of his performances did Berger identify himself as a police officer; offer any comment on Department policies or operations; make any reference to any other member of the Department; nor claim to be speaking for or in any way representing the Department. Although various media, in commenting on or describing his performance, referred to him as “the singing cop,” that designation was, so far as the record reveals, theirs, not Berger’s. In his performances Berger’s only purpose was to provide entertainment for willing listeners. He urged no conduct, incited no activity, made no derogatory or inflammatory remarks, advocated no lawlessness and sought no confrontation.

As you could imagine, many found his performances offensive. The NAACP and others organized a picket line, and tried to stop Berger’s performances–potentially by “physical force.”

On February 9 Dr. Burns and approximately 30 persons associated with the N.A.A.C.P. set up a picket line outside the Hilton to protest the continuation of the engagement. They were joined by Bobby Cheeks and eight members of the Baltimore Welfare Rights Organization, of which Cheeks was executive director. The pickets marched in a circle on the sidewalk, carrying placards stating their objections to the show.
As the time for Berger’s performance drew near, some of the pickets or demonstrators entered the hotel and the nightclub itself, with the intention of preventing the performance. In keeping with the policy of the N.A.A.C.P., it was not then the intention of Dr. Burns and his group to resort to violence or other unlawful activity to achieve their goal. On the other hand, Mr. Cheeks and his followers were then prepared, according to Cheeks’ testimony, to go onto the stage and stop the show, by physical force if necessary.

Because of the threat of violence, additional police forces were called in for backup, leaving other posts “unmanned.” The hotel ultimately “cancelled the show.” After the cancellation, the police department received many complaints from the community:

Following the events of February 9, the police department received a number of complaints from black citizens, including Dr. Burns and Mrs. Enolia McMillan, executive director of the Baltimore branch of the N.A.A.C.P., objecting vehemently to a police officer’s being permitted, as they saw it, to offer a public insult to members of their race. These complaints were a matter of serious concern to the Department, which had been engaged since the mid-to late-1960’s in what Deputy Commissioner Bishop L. Robinson described as a “comprehensive, integrated community approach” to improving its previously strained relations with the black citizens of Baltimore. The Department feared that its community relations efforts would be undermined by widespread outrage over Berger’s performances.

The Department asked Berger to “cease all public performances, in any capacity, while on light-duty status.” Berger’s attorney told him that the order was “unconstitutional,” so he refused. The Department once again ordered him to “cease appearing in public wearing blackface on pain of being found in violation of the Department’s rule prohibiting activity on the part of a member of the Department ‘that tends to reflect discredit upon himself or upon the Department.'” Berger refused, and was later reassigned to a desk job, and “stripped of his police powers.”

Berger filed an action under Section 1983, alleging a violation of his First Amendment rights. Applying Pickering, the district court concluded that the speech was on “a matter of public concern,” but “ascribed overpowering weight to the Department’s interests in avoiding future diversions of its resources to cope with threatened disruptions by offended members of Baltimore’s black community of comparable Berger performances, and in maintaining the Department’s hard-earned good relations with that formerly hostile black community.” It ruled for the Department. On appeal, the Fourth Circuit reversed.

The court first concludes that the “artistic expression” was on a matter of public concern–regardless of whether it is “political” in nature:

We think, instead, that in assessing its value for Pickering balancing purposes, this type of off-duty public employee speech has to be accorded the same weight in absolute terms that would be accorded comparable artistic expression by citizens who do not work for the state. And that value, traditionally, has been accorded a great deal of weight, certainly not far below the value accorded political and social commentary and debate . . . . We therefore accord Berger’s speech the value, in absolute terms, that it would be accorded in any citizen, undiminished by the fact here of his state employment.

The Fourth Circuit further rejected the district court’s conclusion about the Department’s interest outweighing the employee’s free speech rights. The court notes that Pickering is not really a perfect fit, because the speech does not criticize or question the employer, and does not cause a “direct disruption of employment relationships” that would stem from “insubordination or disloyalty.” Berger’s speech was in no sense critical of the government:

Instead the speech here was a form of artistic expression wholly unrelated in content to the public employer or its operations, and the threat it assertedly posed to employer interests was not internal disruption by the speech itself, but external disruption by third persons reacting to the speech.

Further, there was no “direct” or “internal disruption” from the speech.

Here not only was the perceived threat of disruption only to external operations and relationships, it was caused not by the speech itself but by threatened reaction to it by offended segments of the public. Short of direct incitements to violence by the very content of public employee speech (in which case the speech presumably would not be within general first amendment protection), we think this sort of threatened disruption by others reacting to public employee speech simply may not be allowed to serve as justification for public employer disciplinary action directed at that speech.

This is a perfect encapsulation of where the University of Oregon’s report went awry. Professor Shurtz’s costume did not cause any sort of disruption, but the punishment was justified by the “threatened reaction” to her costume “by offended segments of the public.” At bottom, the dispute arose only because of the so-called hecklers-veto. The Fourth Circuit addressed this point:

Historically, one of the most persistent and insidious threats to first amendment rights has been that posed by the “heckler’s veto,” imposed by the successful importuning of government to curtail “offensive” speech at peril of suffering disruptions of public order. See Edwards v. South Carolina, 372 U.S. 229, 83 S.Ct. 680, 9 L.Ed.2d 697 (1963); Terminiello v. City of Chicago, 337 U.S. 1, 69 S.Ct. 894, 93 L.Ed. 1131 (1949). Government’s instinctive and understandable impulse to buy its peace—to avoid all risks of public disorder by chilling speech assertedly or demonstrably offensive to some elements of the public—is a recurring theme in first amendment litigation. See, e.g., Lehman v. City of Shaker Heights, 418 U.S. 298, 94 S.Ct. 2714, 41 L.Ed.2d 770 (1974); Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15, 91 S.Ct. 1780, 29 L.Ed.2d 284 (1971); Rowan v. Post Office Department, 397 U.S. 728, 90 S.Ct. 1484, 25 L.Ed.2d 736 (1970); Terminiello v. City of Chicago, 337 U.S. 1, 69 S.Ct. 894, 93 L.Ed. 1131 (1949); Collin v. Smith, 578 F.2d 1197 (7th Cir.1978). Though this “veto” has probably been most frequently exercised through legislation responsive to majority sensibilities, the same assault on first amendment values of course occurs when, as here, it is exercised by executive action responsive to the sensibilities of a minority.
There is a lot packed into the final sentence, written by a court situated in the former capital of the Confederacy. Traditionally, the heckler’s veto was used to shut down the constitutional rights of minorities. To use an extreme example, in Cooper v. Aaron, Arkansas contended that Central High School must remain segregated to prevent rioting mobs from threatening African-American students. The district court actually accepted that rationale, but the Supreme Court rejected it: the Constitution cannot be shut down by hecklers. At some point in American history, this principle was well understood by the left. Unfortunately, recent caselaw has given more power to the heckler’s veto, including a decision from the Ninth Circuit permitting the punishment of a student for wearing an American Flag shirt on Cinco de May, because it offended Mexican students.

The Fourth Circuit ruled that Berger could only be asked, not ordered, to stop performing. The Department has a duty to uphold not only “public order,” but also the “First Amendment”–an argument lost in Eugene:

As indicated, the special dilemma presented for the Police Department here can only excite judicial sympathy. One may well feel—as undoubtedly did the Department—that a little forbearance on the part of Berger, given the special circumstances of his public employment and the hard-earned and presumably still tenuous trust of the black community, would be in order. One may also wonder—as undoubtedly did the Department—whether the outrage being represented to it as that of the “black community” was truly that widely shared and whether a better and more effective response might have been continued public non-violent demonstrations of contempt and outrage by those sufficiently offended.
Nevertheless, however real the dilemma, we think and hold that the Department—after all an agency of the state charged with enforcing the first amendment as well as with maintaining public order—could not respond as it did consistently with the first amendment, once Berger had declined to forbear and stood on his constitutional rights. Those rights of course exist in the unforbearing as well as the forbearing and have in fact undoubtedly been hammered out largely in behalf of the temperamentally unforbearing who are fortunate enough to live in a society that protects their right immediately to “stand on their rights.”

What should the Department have done? Here is sage advice for the University of Oregon from the Fourth Circuit:

An appropriate Department response, perhaps the only one, wholly consistent with the first amendment, would have been instead to say to those offended by Berger’s speech that their right to protest that speech by all peaceable means would be as stringently safeguarded by the Department as would be Berger’s right to engage in it. We have no illusions that this would have been a satisfactory response, nor that it *1002 may not have led to some of the very disruption of operations and resources that the Department feared. But it would not only have been the most sound response constitutionally, it would have been an eminently practical one for any of those offended by Berger’s speech who were at least willing to consider the wider implications of the principle for which they at least implicitly contended: that offensive speech may properly be curbed by exerting this form of leverage upon public employers. But this is a device as readily seized upon by one group in society as another, and is one more readily available in most times to majority than to minority groups.

Would this not have been a far more productive use of resources, than launching an inquisition to punish a tenured professor?

The opinion closes with a fitting vignette from the Fifth Circuit:

There are of course many illustrations of this, but a particularly apt one for this purpose is that considered by the Fifth Circuit in Battle v. Mulholland, 439 F.2d 321 (5th Cir.1971). There a black police officer in a small Mississippi town had been discharged by the town officials because of the town fathers’ concern, prompted by complaints, and probably justified, that his conduct would exacerbate an already tense racial situation in the town. Noting that this “type of restrictive response, based on theoretical reactions by others” to conduct protected by the first amendment had “long been condemned,” the court held the discharge constitutionally impermissible. We think that the principle applied there is precisely that one applicable here, though figuratively, the shoe here is on the other foot.

Imagine that. Oh, and the ACLU of Maryland represented Mr. Berger. Where is the ACLU today on this issue?

The Ninth Circuit has not addressed Berger directly–though it did address a similar case from the Tenth Circuit (Flanagan) in the context of a police officer’s extra-curricular porno web site. But a concurring opinion by Judge Canby favorably cited Berger:

The majority opinion states that to the extent that Flanagan and Berger “minimize the potential for an actual effect on the efficiency and efficacy of police department functions arising from public perceptions of the inappropriate activities of police officers, they are severely undermined by Roe.” Supra, p. 929 n. 7. The rationale of Flanagan and Berger, however, was not that disruption was minimal, but that as part of the heckler’s veto it could not support discipline of the employee. . . . In my view, the rationale of Flanagan and Berger is not only sound, but constitutionally required. We should apply those principles and hold that Dible’s expressive website conduct was an unconstitutional ground for his discharge.

Dible v. City of Chandler, 515 F.3d 918, 934 (9th Cir. 2008)

The University of Oregon’s report makes no mention of any of these cases. For a moment, try to compare the state’s interest in Berger )preventing actual violent riots), with the University of Oregon’s interest (preventing a “racially hostile environment” and “sense of anxiety and mistrust” among students). The report’s Pickering analysis is pathetically wrong. In a different time, these dynamics would have been viewed as part of a robust academic environment, where difficult questions were addressed in class. No longer.

The Ninth Circuit has addressed a related question about allegedly-harassing speech that is not aimed at an individual. An all-awesome panel with Justice O’Connor, and her former law clerks, Alex Kozinski and Sandra Ikuta, ruled that three racially charged emails sent by a college professors over a list-serve, that were not specifically aimed at any of the complainants, could not give rise to a harassment claim. Rather they were “directed to the college community,” and thus had wide-ranging protections of free speech.  See also Gleason v. Mesirow Financial, 118 F.3d 1134 (7th Cir. 1997) (“the impact of ‘second-hand harassment’ is obviously not as great as the impact of harassment directed at the plaintiff”). Students claiming offense to something they haven’t seen personally is far too attenuated to justify an abridgment of the First Amendment.

Judge Kozinski’s analysis offers sage advice to the Univeristy of Oregon. Read it all:

Indeed, precisely because Kehowski’s ideas fall outside the mainstream, his words sparked intense debate: Colleagues emailed responses, and Kehowski replied; some voiced opinions in the editorial pages of the local paper; the administration issued a press release; and, in the best tradition of higher learning, students protested. The Constitution embraces such a heated exchange of views, even (perhaps especially) when they concern sensitive topics like race, where the risk of conflict and insult is high. See R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul, 505 U.S. 377, 391, 112 S.Ct. 2538, 120 L.Ed.2d 305 (1992). Without the right to stand against society’s most strongly-held convictions, the marketplace of ideas would decline into a boutique of the banal, as the urge to censor is greatest where debate is most disquieting and orthodoxy most entrenched. See, e.g., Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652, 667, 45 S.Ct. 625, 69 L.Ed. 1138 (1925); id. at 673, 45 S.Ct. 625 (Holmes, J., dissenting). The right to provoke, offend and shock lies at the core of the First Amendment.

This is particularly so on college campuses. Intellectual advancement has traditionally progressed through discord and dissent, as a diversity of views ensures that ideas survive because they are correct, not because they are popular. Colleges and universities—sheltered from the currents of popular opinion by tradition, geography, tenure and monetary endowments—have historically fostered that exchange. But that role in our society will not survive if certain points of view may be declared beyond the pale. “Teachers and students must always remain free to inquire, to study and to evaluate, to gain new maturity and understanding; otherwise our civilization will stagnate and die.” Keyishian v. Bd. of Regents of the Univ. of the State of N.Y., 385 U.S. 589, 603, 87 S.Ct. 675, 17 L.Ed.2d 629 (1967) (quoting Sweezy v. New Hampshire, 354 U.S. 234, 250, 77 S.Ct. 1203, 1 L.Ed.2d 1311 (1957)). We have therefore said that “[t]he desire to maintain a sedate academic environment … [does not] justify limitations on a teacher’s freedom to express himself on *709 political issues in vigorous, argumentative, unmeasured, and even distinctly unpleasant terms.” Adamian v. Jacobsen, 523 F.2d 929, 934 (9th Cir.1975).

We therefore doubt that a college professor’s expression on a matter of public concern, directed to the college community, could ever constitute unlawful harassment and justify the judicial intervention that plaintiffs seek. See Eugene Volokh, Comment, Freedom of Speech and Workplace Harassment, 39 UCLA L. Rev. 1791, 1849–55 (1992). Harassment law generally targets conduct, and it sweeps in speech as harassment only when consistent with the First Amendment. See R.A.V., 505 U.S. at 389–90, 112 S.Ct. 2538. For instance, racial insults or sexual advances directed at particular individuals in the workplace may be prohibited on the basis of their non-expressive qualities, Saxe, 240 F.3d at 208, as they do not “seek to disseminate a message to the general public, but to intrude upon the targeted [listener], and to do so in an especially offensive way,” Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.S. 474, 486, 108 S.Ct. 2495, 101 L.Ed.2d 420 (1988). See, e.g., Flores, 324 F.3d at 1133, 1135; Meritor Sav. Bank, FSB v. Vinson, 477 U.S. 57, 60, 73, 106 S.Ct. 2399, 91 L.Ed.2d 49 (1986). But Kehowski’s website and emails were pure speech; they were the effective equivalent of standing on a soap box in a campus quadrangle and speaking to all within earshot. Their offensive quality was based entirely on their meaning, and not on any conduct or implicit threat of conduct that they contained.

It’s easy enough to assert that Kehowski’s ideas contribute nothing to academic debate, and that the expression of his point of view does more harm than good. But the First Amendment doesn’t allow us to weigh the pros and cons of certain types of speech. Those offended by Kehowski’s ideas should engage him in debate or hit the “delete” button when they receive his emails. They may not invoke the power of the government to shut him up.

Perhaps the most troubling aspect of the University of Oregon’s recent decision is the deafening silence by the academy. There has been not a single statement by anyone at the University of Oregon raising any red flags. This should not be surprising because half of that faculty called on Shurtz to resign. Other than my blog post, I’ve seen only a few posts by Brian LeiterPaul Caron, Glenn Reynolds, Ann Althouse, and Tom Smith, as well as a few tweets. A few professors have emailed me privately, so I suspect there are many more that are incensed by this incident. There needs to be more outrage here.

My thanks to Hans Bader for sharing a number of these helpful precedents.